Friday, April 7, 2023

A Tale of Two Courts: Eleven Distinctions in Search of a Difference

 

by John Otrompke, JD(*)

Full fathom five thy father lies;

Of his bones are coral made;

Those are pearls that were his eyes:

Nothing of him that doth fade

But doth suffer a sea-change

Into something rich and strange.

 

- Shakespeare, “The Tempest” (1610)

Introduction

In 2019, Supreme Court of the UK delivered two resounding rebukes to its executive when it tried to exercise its discretion, whereas the Supreme Court of the US allowed the executive to proceed under somewhat similar circumstances. Why? And what does it tell us about how emergency power is used in the two countries?

This study therefore addresses the question, “Can the simple inability of one party in the legislature to convince the other party than an emergency exists be properly deemed an emergency in itself by the executive?”

This presentation examines the treatment of executive emergency powers in the UK and the US by comparing 3 different cases: Sierra Club v Trump (the proposed wall on the Southern border)(1) and Miller I and II (the Brexit prorogation cases, which followed some 5 indeterminate votes on Brexit that were essentially coin flips). With the goal of determining why Miller 1 and 2 didn’t turn out like Sierra Club, I then examine 15 candidates for significant constitutional distinction between the American and British Constitutions, and conclude that precisely none of them account for the different outcomes (Table 1). The outcome in Miller 1 was determined by its facts. That is, had the facts of Sierra Club arisen in the British Supreme Court, the case would likely have come out the same way.

The reason Miller I came out as it did, even though Parliament has generally deigned to permit the Prime Minister to exercise discretionary prerogative powers over foreign affairs, is that the no-deal Brexit which seemed imminent at the time would have resulted in changes to the rights of British subjects across a wide swath of substantive legal areas. That is a factual distinction, not a constitutional one.

This presentation then examines 9 areas of recent chaotic flux in British constitutional law (one of them being Brexit itself), and determines that only one of them accounted for the outcome in Miller 2, inasmuch as it diverged from Sierra Club (Table 2). But that source of chaotic disruption in the British Constitution, the Fixed Term Parliaments Act of 2011, purported to make the two Constitutions more similar, not more different. It was ineffectual, and it’s gone now, having been repealed in 2022.  

I then briefly conduct a similar inquiry regarding the obverse question: how would the US Supreme Court treat an American Brexit?

Having learned about how constitutional emergencies are handled in the American and British Supreme Courts, my project is to then examine British examples from relevant time periods and American examples during 8 recent constitutional crises (Table 3).   

Sierra Club v Trump

All three of the cases came to the respective Supreme Courts under circumstances giving rise to allegations of nativism, in environments in which immigration was controversial, and in both, the executive sought to exercise its discretion using language sometimes reserved for emergencies.

In Sierra Club, former Pres. Trump repeatedly sought funds from the US legislature “for the construction of a border barrier,” but did not receive enough funding, leading to a 35-day partial government shutdown. Sierra Club at 676. He then decided to "reprogram funds appropriated by Congress to the Department of Defense…for Army personnel needs” to build a wall on the border with Mexico, in the southern part of the US.

Section 8005 of the Department of Defense Appropriations Act of 2019 authorized the Secretary of Defense to transfer funds for military purposes if the Secretary determines that the transfer is "for higher priority items, based on unforeseen military requirements." Reprogramming does not require the declaration of a national emergency. Id at 681. But the US Constitution (art I., § 9, cl. 7) provides that "[n]o Money shall be drawn from the Treasury, but in Consequence of Appropriations made by Law."

The majority of the Ninth Circuit agreed with Sierra Club that the need for funds to build a barrier on the southern border was not “unforeseen.” Sierra Club alleged that the executive’s “use of the reprogrammed funds would injure their members because the noise of construction, additional personnel, visual blight, and negative ecological effects that would accompany a border barrier and its construction would detract from their ability to hike, fish, enjoy the desert landscapes, and observe and study a diverse range of wildlife in areas near the U.S.-Mexico border.” Id at 683.

But the dissent in the Ninth Circuit (which I treat as dispositive), concluded that Sierra Club had no way of redressing any constitutional violation: “neither an implied statutory cause of action under § 8005, nor an equitable cause of action” directly under the Constitution. The dissent also held that Sierra Club’s injury fell “outside of the zone of interests” for purposes of the Administrative Procedure Act. Id at 709.

Miller 1 and the Limits of the Prime Minister’s Power to Engage in Treaty Making

We may observe the first important distinction upon reading the captions of the British cases: R (on the application of Miller and another) v Secretary of State for Exiting the European Union, et al, [2017] UKSC 5 (Miller 1); and R (on the application of Miller) (Appellant) v The Prime Minister (and) Cherry and others (Respondents) v Advocate, et al, [2019] UKSC 41 (Miller 2).

“Mrs. Gina Miller” is a party in both cases; Joanna Cherry, a party only in Miller 2, is a Member of Parliament, but Miller was not. Indeed, the two Miller opinions say almost nothing else at all about Mrs. Gina Miller, noting only that “some of the legal rights which the applicants enjoy under EU law will come to an end” (Miller 1, paragraph 6). However, she is credibly described elsewhere as a “businesswoman.”

The applicants in Miller 1 (including Mrs. Miller) were “supported in their opposition to the appeal by a group deriving rights of residence in the UK under EU law on the basis of their relationship with a British national or with a non-British EU national …[and]  a group deriving rights of residence from persons permitted to reside in the UK because of EU rights, including children and carers.” (Paragraph 8).

Immediately, then, we can see that standing may be treated differently in the two societies. True, Miller 1 points out that some of Mrs. Miller’s legal rights will be affected by a no-deal Brexit. (I summarize the wide variety of substantive legal changes that were wrought below, in the section on factual distinctions, which I find to be determinative). However, the Sierra Club made cogent arguments about the existence of personalized injury in the Supreme Court case, too, such as the loss of opportunities to enjoy wildlife, and organizational standing, as the Sierra Club has expended money in lobbying about the issue of a wall on the southern border. Nevertheless, the Supreme Court tells us that the plaintiffs in that case “lack a cause of action.” The dissent in the Ninth Circuit opinion, which I presume the Supreme Court endorses, lays the cause to legislative intent. By contrast, it seems the parties in Miller 1 have a very direct cause of action, with little need for the delegation of intermediate authority or permission from the legislature. (As mentioned, in Miller 2, applicant Joanna Cherry is also an MP).

 Therefore, it seems safe to say that the two societies may regard standing (oft criticized as an unfair requirement in the US) differently, especially since legislator standing is so weak in the U.S. anyway. (2).If it had not been for the lack of a cause of action, the US Supreme Court may have dismissed on grounds of justiciability.  But the UK Supreme Court found the issues to be justiciable in Miller 1 (paragraph 3) and Miller 2 (paragraph 52).

However, the difference in access to the courts did not make the difference between the Brexit cases and Trump’s wall. Such a difference was necessary, but not sufficient. In Miller 1, that’s because Parliament has generally allowed the Prime Minister to retain executive prerogative regarding foreign affairs. “[M]inisters generally enjoy a power freely to enter into and to terminate treaties without recourse to Parliament…[However,] ministers are not normally entitled to exercise any power they might otherwise have if it results in a change in UK domestic law, unless statute, ie an Act of Parliament, so provides.” (Paragraph 5).

Changes in domestic British law described by the Supreme Court included employment protection such as the Working Time Directive, and the benefit of the ‘four freedoms’ (free movement of people, goods and capital, and freedom to provide services)(paragraph 70); the recognition and enforcement of judgments in matrimonial matters and the matters of parental responsibility (paragraph 71); the right to stand for selection or later election to the European Parliament, and the right to vote in European elections (paragraph 72); and the right of men who have had sex with men to give blood (paragraph 131).

Miller 2 and the Limits of the Prime Minister’s Power to Manage Parliament

Actually, Miller I and II concerned two different forms of executive discretion in the British Constitution: the power of the Prime Minister to engage in treaty-making sans an act of Parliament (Miller I), and the power of the Prime Minister to temporarily prorogue Parliament (which means to prevent Parliament from meeting for a period of time) (Miller II). In Miller 2, the UK Supreme Court recognized prorogation as a “prerogative power exercised by the Crown,” noting that the last monarch to personally announce prorogation in Parliament was Queen Victoria in 1854. (Paragraph 3).   

It is hardly a constitutional crisis that the Supreme Court ruled the prorogation invalid. After all, an 11-year prorogation was at the root of the English Civil War (which was shortly followed by another prorogation by Oliver Cromwell). However, the Supreme Court noted that the average length of a modern day prorogation was under 10 days (paragraph 18), and concluded that the Prime Minister’s decision to prorogue for three of five weeks before Brexit was to take place “had the effect of frustrating or preventing the constitutional role of Parliament in holding the Government to account.” (Paragraph 55).

The US Constitution, Article II, Section 3 allows for prorogation; but it has never been used. (3) Therefore, while the power of the Prime Minister to prorogue Parliament is an important distinction between the American and British Constitutions, this distinction did not make the difference in outcomes in the cases, because the Supreme Court did not permit the prorogation to go forward.

However, the outcome in Miller 2 brings us to the discussion of an area of recent chaotic British constitutional change which made all the difference in the Brexit cases: the customary constitutional power of the Prime Minister to require a new election general election, by declaring a vote on a matter the Minister considers important (such as a no-deal Brexit) a “matter of confidence.” 

Historically, and today, this customary power marks a very significant distinction from the US Constitution, but in 2019, the Fixed Term Parliaments Act of 2011 (FTPA) made the two constitutions more similar; Parliament even experimented with requiring a 2/3 supermajority. It was ironically that similarity that made the difference in the outcome of Miller 2 and Sierra Club.

Historically, and today, the Prime Minister had another prerogative power: to order the dissolution of Parliament, followed by a general election. (Miller 2, paragraph 4).

In Commonwealth constitutions, the executive has kind of a duty to manage Parliament (although that duty is placed in Canada on another official, the Governor General):

“The governor general has a responsibility to ensure that Parliament is allowed to function. This is why she has a right to summon Parliament if a prime minister takes too long to do so, particularly following an election. If a Parliament ceases to function, the governor general has the prerogative power to dissolve it and order fresh elections in the hopes that the new Parliament will be able to function.”

Andrew Heard, The Governor General’s Suspension of Parliament, in “Parliamentary Democracy in Crisis,” (Russell and Sossin, eds), p. 58, University of Toronto Press, 2009.

But the Prime Minister’s prerogative powers are, like everything else in the British Constitution, subject to Parliamentary sovereignty. At the time of the Brexit cases, the FTPA provided for general elections every five years unless either the House of Commons voted by a 2/3 majority for earlier elections; or the House of Commons voted “no confidence” in the Prime Minister. (Paragraph 5).

Historically, and today, the Prime Minister would have been able to make a vote on a no-deal Brexit a “matter of confidence,” and if the Minister did not get what they wanted, to make everybody in the House of Commons (including the Minister themself) immediately subject to new elections. (4).

That may have brought us a “Miller 3,” but in the absence of prior action by Parliament, I  believe the UK Supreme Court would have permitted the dissolution, and the American and British cases would have come out the same. (In fact, as I explain below, the FTPA did not prevent early elections right before Brexit).

Note that the UK Supreme Court could have, but didn’t, allow greater flexibility in the executive’s prorogation powers in light of Parliament’s elimination of the ‘vote of confidence’ convention.

It would be nice to say that fixed term parliaments are just another natural step in the progressive evolution of Parliamentary sovereignty, but it’s gone now.

Cross-Atlantic Distinctions in a Sea of Chaos

The UK has been positively awash in recent years in the ebb and flow of what could only be described as chaotic constitutional change, following admission to the EU in 1973. (See Table 2, describing 9 areas of chaotic flux in British constitutional law). This maelstrom of back-and-forth disruption has been prompted, according to some, by nativist backlash against the UK’s submission to the jurisdiction of several international courts, the EU’s European Court of Justice and the European Court of Human Rights (which exists by reason of another, non-EU instrument, the European Convention on Human Rights), not to mention the UN’s International Court of Justice. (5). Facets of the storm have included nominal devolution of power to the constituent countries of the UK other than England (Ireland, Scotland and Wales) (6); the transformation of the Appellate Committee of the House of Lords into the UK Supreme Court in 2009 (7); the enactment of the Fixed Term Parliaments Act in 2011; Brexit; and the repeal of the FTPA in 2022.

Throughout all of that, what has not changed at all, even with admission into the EU more than half a century ago, is what has been absolutely bedrock fundamental about the British Constitution since the “Glorious Revolution” of 1688: Parliamentary sovereignty. (8)

                Put simply, Parliament is all-powerful in the British Constitution, and requires no supermajority to do virtually whatever the legislature wants. In point of fact, usually it is the House of Commons which is Supreme. “[T]he Parliament Act was passed in August 1911, removing the power of the House of Lords to reject money bills and replacing its veto over other bills with merely a power of delay.” (9).

                One may verify that this power of a simple legislative majority makes the British Constitution far more flexible than its American counterpart by examining the status of the right to bear arms found in the English Bill of Rights, which followed the English Civil War and was passed in 1689 during the Glorious Revolution.  

                While the right is rightly viewed as “fundamental” by many American legal scholars today, in part because of its inclusion in the English Bill of Rights, it has been seriously controlled in the UK since 1910, and thereafter.  This illustrates the “wrecking ball” effect of the power of a simple majority vote in the UK, wreaking havoc on the British Constitution.

                Speaking of Parliamentary sovereignty, one might wonder, is it Parliament that is supreme, or the people, or perhaps the electorate?  It is Parliament. With the Septennial Act of 1715, the House of Commons extended its own life from three to seven years. (10)

                Because of Parliamentary sovereignty, judicial review in the UK is limited. Courts can require a degree of clarity in laws passed by Parliament. Since the time of Edward Coke, a British judge who wrote even before the present British constitutional settlement, British jurists and legal scholars have expressed qualms about Parliamentary sovereignty whenever it violated a principle called “the rule of law” (a set of not always well-defined norms associated with a limited executive). (11) Since the time of Dr. Bonham’s Case, 8 Co. Rep. 107, 77 Eng. Rep. 638 (Winter 1610), decided by Coke as Chief Justice in the Court of Common Pleas, British courts have used a concept they call the ultra vires doctrine to strike down state action they think improper. (12)

For example, British courts could say of executive action that had been delegated by Parliament, that it was illegal, because Parliament did not really tell the Crown to do that. Or the courts could say to Parliament, “You didn’t really mean to do that, did you? We assume you didn’t really mean to do that, because it would violate the ‘rule of law’ principle, or some other Parliamentary law.” But if the legislature passes a law and says, “No, we really, really mean it,” the British courts are supposed to recognize the authority of Parliament. (13).

                                                             Vetoes

Not only is judicial review of Parliamentary action limited, but the UK sort of lacks an executive veto power. While law in the UK is nominally made “by the Crown in Parliament,” no monarch or Prime Minister has exercised the veto power since Queen Anne’s refusal of royal assent to the Scottish Militia Bill in 1707. (14) During the Brexit controversy, Prime Minister Johnson spoke of potentially withholding the Royal Assent to legislation preventing a no-deal Brexit. That might have been a constitutional crisis, but he didn’t actually do it. (15)

Hence, there is no veto in the British Constitution. While classical British scholars say that “the Crown in Parliament” (that is, two houses, the House of Lords and the House of Commons) constitutes the tripartite separation of powers that gives balance to the British Constitution, it is rumored that the British monarch has less influence than one might expect with the Prime Minister, who after all is chosen by a vote of MPs in the House of Commons.

I mentioned above the reduction in influence of the House of Lords. Accordingly, it is really just one body in the UK that makes primary law: the House of Commons. (16)

The Prime Minister will reliably not veto an act of Parliament. However, another customary constitutional practice, the rule of Crown initiative, means that only the Minister, not actually the House of Commons, can propose new forms of public spending or revenue raising. (17) 

Musing on Parliamentary sovereignty, one might be excused for wondering, if God is all-powerful, can he create a stone so heavy that even he cannot lift it? The answer is no.  Parliament is always free to change its mind later. The Fixed Term Parliaments Act changed the law so that a 2/3 supermajority was required to call for elections earlier. But how many votes did it take to pass the Early Parliamentary General Election Act 2019, and simply bypass the FTPA, just this once, after the Prime Minister tried but failed to get the 2/3 majority? When one considers that it later took only a simple majority to repeal the FTPA in 2022, it seems that one is transacting in cave phantoms when one tries to change the bedrock principle of the British Constitution.

Membership in the EU kind of was a profound constitutional change, since “[t]he 1972 Act… authorises a dynamic process by which, without further primary legislation (and, in some cases, even without any domestic legislation), EU law not only becomes a source of UK law, but actually takes precedence over all domestic sources of UK law” (Miller 1, paragraph 60); but this did not alter the fundamental principle of UK law, because Parliament was always free to take the chains off, by passing a law leaving the EU.

Comparative Crises

So what have we learned about emergency power? “Can the simple inability of one party in the legislature to convince the other party than an emergency exists be properly deemed an emergency in itself by the executive?” The answer to this question in the UK is yes, except not while the FTPA was in effect. In the US, sometimes yes, especially in areas of foreign relations, especially because the legislature was able to decide after Watergate that the foreign policy “emergency” did not justify the executive’s emergency powers.

What kind of emergency powers model does the US have? Many constitutional theorists describe three models, dating from the work of Carl Schmitt (author of “Political Theology: Four Chapters on the Theory of Sovereignty,” trans. George Schwab [Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2005]): the extralegal Lockean model, the Machiavellian neo-Roman model of temporary dictatorship, and the legal model. (18)

The US has a variant on the Machiavellian neo-Roman model, in which the Supreme Court and/or Congress reins in the exceptional powers of the executive when they feel it is the right time to do so (even though the judiciary / legislature will not enforce laws restraining the executive during an emergency, which may seem to be a lot of the time).

What about the UK? The UK doesn’t really have emergencies, at least not constitutional emergencies, because it is so easy to change the law, and it seems utterly impossible to change what is bedrock fundamental. But one could look at the period of Northern Ireland exceptionality (in Marshall v UK, a 9- year derogation in Northern Ireland was approved by the European Court of Human Rights) (19); the Belmarsh case (20); the creation of the human rights committee described in Loevy (21), or the recent experience with quarantine and COVID, to see that British practice is sui generis, and allows the UK the flexibility to adopt any of the three models it feels appropriate, depending on the circumstances. (History will tell us whether devolution did not mark the advent of a new constitutional settlement in the UK).

But of all the areas of chaotic disruption in the UK Constitution that played a role in the Brexit cases, the one that came closest to a constitutional crisis was the Fixed Term Parliaments Act, and that’s gone now.

Regarding the relative prevalence of constitutional emergencies in the UK in recent years, the topsy-turvy quality of recent Constitutional change in the UK is precisely a product of Parliamentary sovereignty, just as the relative inertia of the US Constitution through 8 recent constitutional crises in the US is a product of the super-majoritarian requirement (see Table 3).

The relativity can’t be ignored: from an American perspective, the British are subjecting themselves to a soaking daydream of constitutional ephemerality, drifting back and forth seemingly without a fixed end in mind, while the Americans are positively helpless to change the course dictated by the supermajority requirement, emergencies- mass shootings, for example- notwithstanding.

                                                         American Brexit

I have now examined 15 candidates for significant distinction between the American and British Constitutions, and have concluded that none of them drove the different outcomes in cases, although the difference in facts did: Brexit would have affected British law and the rights of individuals, and therefore required action by Parliament. That is, had the facts in Sierra Club arisen in the UK Supreme Court, I think the case would have come out just as it did in the US.

But what about the obverse, that is, an American Brexit? At first, it is difficult to imagine a situation in which the U.S. would voluntarily transfer as much sovereignty to an international union as the UK transferred to the EU and its Court of Justice. (The U.S. is not even a party to the International Criminal Court). But on second thought, is it really? Many of the grievances that arose in the UK about the transfer of sovereignty echo complaints that arose some 25 years ago about accession to the World Trade Organization, which have long since been utterly muffled by more than 20 years of constitutional crisis following the atrocities of Sept. 11, several shocking and constitutionally controversial elections, COVID, and an epidemic of mass shootings.

Still, if the facts of Brexit came up in the US Supreme Court, I think it would have come out differently from the decisions in the UK. The US Constitution (Article II, Section 2, Clause 2) empowers the President as the primary negotiator of treaties (although it takes a two-thirds supermajority of the Senate to render a treaty binding with the force of federal law). I think the US Supreme court would let the executive go ahead and withdraw from such treaty. (Therefore, my goal is to examine domestic and international cases concerning the WTO and the US, as well as the UK, to explore my hypothesis). In that sense, from the perspective of an American Brexit, maybe legislative sovereignty does make all the difference after all.

                                                            Conclusion

Note that the political outcome of the controversies associated with the cases discussed above was reversed: in Miller 1 and 2, where the executive was not permitted to decide what the emergency was in the context of legislative uncertainty, Brexit happened; in Sierra Club, where the executive was given that discretion, the wall on the southern border was never finished. Ultimately, perhaps the will of the electorate was different in the two countries.

And at the end of the day, what difference did Brexit make? With the recent UK Bill of Rights having failed, the UK is still part of the European Court of Human Rights (the Strasbourg court), and the process of devolution is still very much alive, its future portent as yet undetermined. Britain still has a relatively unsettled Constitution.

Having identified the two important differences between the cases and Constitutions in Miller and Sierra Club, one factual (the broad impact on British subjects’ rights of a no-deal Brexit) and one legal (the vote of confidence convention, as cancelled by the FTPA), we may now turn to our central inquiry: what are the similarities and differences in the ways the two societies’ legal cultures address executive emergency powers in an emergency?

The rest of this treatise will compare the exercise of emergency power in distinct milieux to observe the advantages and pitfalls of both systems: in the UK before the EU; after the EU but before the FTPA; during the EU and the FTPA; and after both. On the American side, we will examine a variety of circumstances before Watergate; between Watergate and 9/11; and post-9/11.

I will also look at several instances where emergency powers were spoken of in the UK, (1) the period of Northern Ireland exceptionality; (2) the Belmarsh case; (3) the creation of the human rights committee described in Loevy; (4) Brexit; (5) and the recent experience with quarantine and COVID; and in the US, (6) Vietnam and Watergate; (7) accession to the WTO; (8) several shocking elections (Bush v Gore, Trump v Clinton, and Trump v Biden); (9) 9/11; (10) COVID; and (11) the gun violence epidemic.

                                                            Table 1

15 Candidates for Distinctions Between the British and US Constitutions

1.       Standing (civilian and legislative).

2.       Prorogation (treated differently in US Constitution).

3.       The UK had surrendered some of her jurisdiction over her members to several international courts, located outside the UK. Then again, it has been argued that the US surrendered some of their jurisdiction by subscribing to the World Trade Organization.

4.       Devolution. Federalism is actually a similarity between the two countries. The Supreme Court of the UK concluded that it does not matter whether devolution is a valid argument against the government action. 

5.       The new British Supreme Court’s increased mandatory jurisdiction, compared with the US.

6.        All of the members on the UK Supreme Court are Lords.

7.       Parliamentary sovereignty (kind of is not a distinction that makes a difference, without looking at the divergent facts in the two situations).

8.       The House of Lords cannot prevent a law from being made, but may fatally delay it; this is kind of made up for the fact that the Lords make up the membership of the Supreme Court.

9.       The difference in the individualized rights view of the right to bear arms in the Constitution of both countries is not determinative of the different outcomes.

10.   Power of Parliament to extend its own term with a simple majority vote.

11.   Judicial review is more limited, and the term ultra vires has a different connotation.

12.   The UK lacks an effective executive veto power.

13.   Rule of crown initiative versus US cases on impoundment.

14.   The customary practice of votes of confidence and the power to dissolve the legislature and compel new elections.

15.   The facts of the situations (that Brexit involved potentially much broader changes to the rights of British people than the wall on the southern border) are significant, and do determine the divergent outcomes in the cases, in the sense that Sierra Club, with its divergent facts, would have come out much the same in the British Supreme Court.

                                                                        Table 2

                                 9 Areas of Chaotic Flux in British Constitutional Law

1.       International court jurisdiction.

2.       Joining the European Union

3.       Devolution.

4.       The existence of the new British Supreme Court, its title, seal and building

5.       The Supreme Court’s new mandatory jurisdiction

6.       The changing nature of the House of Lords and the membership of the Supreme Court

7.       The Fixed Term Parliaments Act.

8.       Repeal of the FTPA.

9.       Brexit.

                                                            Table 3

                                    8 Recent American Constitutional Crises

1.       1. Vietnam and Watergate

2.      2.  Accession to the World Trade Organization

3.       3. Bush v Gore

4.       4. 9/11 and the USA PATRIOT Act

5.       5. Trump v Clinton

6.       6. COVID

7.       7. Trump v Biden

8.       8. The gun violence epidemic


*  John J. Otrompke, JD is a bar applicant in New York and a member of the Society of American Law Teachers. He may be reached at John_Otrrompke@yahoo.com.  

1. The U.S. Supreme Court issued a very brief opinion in the case and granted the executive’s request for a stay on the Ninth Circuit’s judgement. Trump v Sierra Club, 140 S. Ct. 1 (2019). The case became moot when President Biden was elected. Because the Supreme Court justified its decision by the argument that “the plaintiffs have no cause of action,” this essay will treat the dissenting opinion in the Ninth Circuit as controlling for the purposes of this experiment in contrast. Sierra Club v Trump, 929 F.3d 670 (2019) at 708.

2. See Kucinich v Obama, 821 F. Supp. 2d 110 (2011); Kucinich v Bush, 236 F. Supp. 2d 1, 23-24 (DDC 2002), citing Chenoweth v Clinton, 181 F.3d 112 (DDC 1999); Johnson v. Eisentrager, 339 U.S. 763 (1950).

3. See also the discussion in Federalist No. 69 by Alexander Hamilton.

4. Under the FTPA, the House of commons could vote no confidence in the Minister, but that vote could not be tied to any other vote. That is, the Minister “could no longer designate any other vote (say on its budget, or a particular legislative proposal) as a ‘matter of confidence’ and threaten a dissolution if it lost the vote.” -Private correspondence with Paul Evans, retired Clerk of the Commons (on file with the author).

5. While I treat submission to foreign courts as a source of constitutional disruption, I treat it as not a difference between the two Constitutions, since similar arguments have been made in the US about submission to the jurisdiction of the World Trade Organization.

6. In 1998 in Northern Ireland and Scotland, but in 2006 in Wales. Note that the devolution settlements required of  “the devolved governments and legislatures that they must not act in breach of EU law.” Miller 1, paragraph 128. The UK Supreme Court held in Miller 1 that “the devolved legislatures do not have a parallel legislative competence in relation to withdrawal” that was infringed by the Prime Minister’s decision to leave the EU without an Act of Parliament. (Paragraph 130). Hence, I treat devolution as not determinative of the difference in outcomes. Because devolution might loosely be compared with federalism in the US, I treat it as not an important distinction between the two Constitutions.

7. “Building the UK's New Supreme Court: National and Comparative Perspectives,” Andrew Le Sueur (ed.), (Oxford, 2004). The new Supreme Court has a new building and seal in addition to its new name. It is said to sometimes complain about a considerable increase in mandatory jurisdiction. “Human Rights and the United Kingdom Supreme Court,” Brice Dickson (Oxford University 2013), p. 4, note 20; p. 5. That is an important distinction from the US Supreme Court, but not determinative of the difference in outcomes. Another potential distinction: it could be said that membership on the Supreme Court- still all Lords- is tainted by the historically-suspect classification associated with the aristocracy. But that has been changing, after “reforms after 1997 removed all but ninety hereditary peerages, with new hereditary peers elected to the House by their fellow hereditaries.” “The Impossible Office? The History of the British Prime Minister,” Anthony Seldon (Cambridge University Press 2021), p. 186. Both the increase in mandatory jurisdiction in the new UK Supreme Court and the nature of the House of Lords could be significant distinctions from the US Constitution, and both mark chaotic disruption in the British Constitution. I treat the differences in the make-up of the two Supreme Courts as significant but not determinative, because I credit with good faith the transparent reasoning of the British Supreme Court in the Miller cases.

8. An important distinction between the two Constitutions, and one which has not been in flux. Nevertheless, Parliamentary sovereignty kind of doesn’t make the difference in the divergent outcomes in the three cases, unless the disparate facts are considered.

9. “The Impossible Office?”, p. 185.

10. From unwritten to written : transformation in the British Common-Law Constitution, David Jenkins, Vanderbilt Journal of Transnational Law, Vol. 36, No. 3, 2003, pp. 859-870. This power to extend its own term is a distinction from American law, but like the status of gun rights discussed above is only another aspect of Parliamentary sovereignty.

11. “Permanent State of Emergency,” Ryan Alford (McGill-Queen’s University Press, 2018), p. 12

12. The ultra vires notion may play a somewhat different role in American law, but if it is a distinction, it did not cause the disparate outcome in the cases.

13. From unwritten to written, p. 866.

14. Braking the Law: Is There, and Should There Be, an Executive Veto Over Legislation in the UK Constitution, Paul Evans (The Constitution Unit, University College London, October 2020), p. 8.

15. The lack of a veto power is certainly a big distinction between the two Constitutions, but it didn’t make the difference in the outcome of the cases, because Parliament usually permits the Prime Minister the power to conduct foreign affairs anyway.

16. For purposes of this article, I consider the comparative weakness of the British upper house to be not a distinction, because the British Constitution allocates the membership of the Supreme Court to the House of Lords, giving that chamber relatively more power in relation to the Prime Minister and the House of Commons.

17. Braking the Law, p. 19. The rule of Crown initiative could be compared and contrasted with US cases on impoundment. Train v City of New York, 420 US 35 (1975). See also the Impoundment Control Act and the Congressional Budget Act of 1974. The impoundment cases may indeed have played a role in Sierra Club had the Supreme Court more thoroughly developed its thinking in the area; but I treat the rule of Crown initiative and impoundment law as not determining the divergent outcomes in the cases under discussion.

18. “Emergencies in Public Law,” Karin Loevy (Cambridge University Press 2016), p. 24 et seq. See also The Emergency Constitution, Bruce Ackerman (Yale Faculty Scholarship Series 121 (2004); Providing for the Unexpected: Constitutional Emergency Provisions, Oren Gross (Israel Yearbook on Human Rights 2004); Constitutional Exceptionalism and the Common Law, Thomas Poole Law (Society and Economy Working Papers 14, London School of Economics and Political Science, 2008).

19. “Emergencies in Public Law,” p. 104

20. Id pp. 98-99.

21. Id p. 122 et seq.

Thursday, October 6, 2022

Reflections on a Proposed International Constitutional Court

  by John Otrompke, JD

    Following is my commentary on Prof. Richard Albert's new paper, "Does the World Need an International Constitutional Court?" 

    Prof. Albert was kind enough to extend to me a general invitation to come to Austin, Texas to present my research comparing the treatment of executive discretion by two Supreme Courts: that of the US in Sierra Club v Trump (Trumps' wall) and the UK in Cherry v Solicitor (Brexit).

    Prof. Albert's text can be found here

https://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/papers.cfm?abstract_id=4198354

    I conclude, among other objections, that an International Constitutional Court is not a good idea, because it could be used to justify aggressive warfare, which is otherwise a grave international crime.

Dear Prof. Albert, 

    I enjoyed reading your recent article, “Does the World Need an International Constitutional Court?” Thank you also for extending to me the general invitation to comment.

While I learned much from your article, I respectfully disagree with your thesis that such a court would be a good idea, although I agree with your conclusion that the idea should not be rejected without more thinking.

Here is where I disagree.

When I studied international criminal law under the late Prof. Cherif Bassiouni at DePaul, it seemed emphasized that peremptory norms, or jus cogens, were not political; that is, they were not based on what kind of government a country had. Grave crimes such as crimes against humanity or other forms of human rights abuse were subject to prosecution before the International Criminal Court, but no particular form of government is privileged over another (eg, democracy, socialism, etc).

International law came of age during the Cold War, and it was important the form of a land’s government not present a justification for superpowers to invade and bring about regime change, possibly justifying what would otherwise be a violation of the grave crime against aggressive warfare.

And historically, notions about democracy and its idealization often did provide an excuse for colonizing countries in the west to intervene in traditional societies, in Africa, the Pacific islands, and elsewhere, to demand that they adopt modern democracy, as a cover for colonizing them and exploiting their natural resources and labor. 

And our own country has a not very good track record for helping democracy to happen in other countries. One of closest allies is Saudi Arabia. And when direct military intervention justified by a perceived need for democratic “regime change” doesn’t work, intelligence agencies will work behind the scenes, such as by putting the Shah of Iran in power.

    Perhaps democracy is stymied because the US began supporting monarchies when the US chose to enter WWI 100 years ago, ignoring Washington’s injunction to avoid the broils of Europe.

Part of the problem is probably one of definition. For example, societies of great variety all over the world call themselves “Republics,” but nobody really agrees as to what that means. As for Plato, I’m not even sure I like his model of a society.

    I’m also not sure that democracy is on the wane. The League of Nations and the UN have been created in the last century. It is kind of a form of global democracy, but perhaps the democracy is stymied or thwarted in the design: votes in the General Assembly often go 150-3 (the 3 being the UK, US and Israel), but the proposals get no traction because of the Security Council.  

    Maybe a modified UN really is the way to create a more democratic world, but the US might not recognize it, and might oppose it, just as the US opposes the International Criminal Court.

However, it’s not a bad idea, and I certainly enjoyed learning about de Gaulle’s referendum, and the regional Constitutional courts you wrote about so eloquently. Thanks again for the opportunity!

~John


Sunday, July 26, 2020

The 2018 NCD on Next Generation Sequencing: Too Little, Too Late?


      The Standard of Care for Cancer Should be Somatic Sequencing at Diagnosis


Because the Standard of Care Should be Better

by John J. Otrompke, JD 


               Within five years, tumor sequencing at the time of a patient’s cancer diagnosis will be the standard of care, according to a number of speakers at several 2020 oncology conferences, including ASCO, BIO and Cancer Progress.

                Both somatic and germline sequencing already form an important part of cancer care, but too often cancer patients do not receive targeted therapies until they have failed on other drugs, at which point it might be too late. (Somatic sequencing is the sequencing of cells from a tumor, while germline sequencing applies to a patient’s normal DNA).

In 2018, a National Coverage Determination (NCD) from CMS provided coverage from federal health payors for somatic sequencing, but it was only conclusive for patients in the late stages of cancer. (Another NCD from January 2020 applied to germline sequencing for breast and ovarian cancer genes).

                But it is important to do sequencing at the time of a patient’s initial diagnosis, so that patients can receive targeted therapies up-front; oncologists hope that up-front treatment with the new therapies will reduce acquired tumor resistance, and substantially improve patients’ results.

                When a patient has experienced an adverse medical result, they can sometimes file suit against their provider, alleging that the provider was less careful than a reasonable provider would have been (in other words, that the provider’s treatment in the case fell below the standard of care). Medical malpractice cases are usually governed by state law, but in some states, it’s possible that triers of fact could consider a federal regulation like a NCD in deciding whether the conduct of an oncologist was reasonable. Under the circumstances forecasted above, a few years from now, the failure to sequence a patient’s tumor at diagnosis could render a provider liable for professional negligence.

“Somatic sequencing at the time of cancer diagnosis will be declared the standard of care within two years. We see alterations in all solid tumors that mandate molecular profiling in everybody,” said  Ezra Cohen, MD, professor of medicine at University of California at San Diego.

“I would consider it the standard of care now for a few cancers, such as acute leukemias and myelodysplastic syndromes,” added Cohen, who participated in a June 10 session called ‘What Was Hot at ASCO?’ at the virtual BIO 2020 conference.

Time for a Scientific Reimbursement Policy

“We have targeted therapies against several low-frequency alterations that occur, such as NTRK fusions which occur in up to 3% of lung cancer cases. The response rates to those therapies are 80% and higher, so not detecting those rare alterations would have a substantial negative effect on the patient,” added Cohen.

“It would be malpractice for a patient to come in with suspected cancer and for us not to have the pathologist look at the tissue and make a diagnosis.  At some point, not doing the fundamental diagnosis to understand cancer would not be acceptable,” explained Razelle Kurzrock, MD, professor of medicine at UCSD.

                But notwithstanding the new drugs like entrectinib, larotrectinib and pembrolizumab, which enjoy tissue-agnostic approval from the FDA under certain circumstances, the importance of early somatic sequencing has not caught on yet in some quarters.

“I’m guessing that the majority of cancer patients in the country are still not sequenced,” said Kurzrock, who is also co-author of articles such as “Challenging Standard-of-Care Paradigms in the Precision Oncology Era,” Subbiah V and Kurzrock R (Trends Cancer. 2018 February ; 4(2): 101–109) (“Between 2003 and 2013, new cancer drugs approved by the European Medicines Agency (EMA) or the Food and Drug Administration (FDA) produced a total mean improvement in overall survival of only 3.4 months relative to the treatments that were available in 2003”).

The recent FDA approval of pembrolizumab for patients with tumor mutational burden high is a case in point. “For all intents and purposes, that approval on June 16 requires sequencing, but the approval is for patients who have failed standard therapy. It’s not going to be a rationale for sequencing up front,” added Kurzrock, who noted that the FDA often approves drugs based on studies done in patients who had already failed other therapies.

“If we’re going to use targeted therapies, we have to learn the lesson of chronic myeloid leukemia (CML), and treat at diagnosis. If you wait two or three years to use therapies we know work on CML, the treatments that give you a 100% response rate and normal life expectancy will encounter much more resistance, and you might get a life expectancy of a year,” explained Kurzrock. “Acquired tumor resistance always happens when you let the cancer evolve.”



Tuesday, May 5, 2020

Three Speech / Article Ideas I've Been Working Up for the Health Care Industry

Please contact me at John_Otrompke@yahoo.com if you would like me to address your organization or its Board of Directors regarding any of these topics, or if you would like me to write an article or white paper.

I have been researching the national coverage decision from CMS regarding next generation sequencing. I had been chatting with the folks from the Personalized Medicine Coalition, and trying to learn what it would take to get more uniform reimbursement for laboratory-designed tests for cancers other than breast and ovarian cancer. Another interesting thing about this area is that the FDA has been asking some companies for proof that these molecular assays work! If widespread, this could a significant departure from the agency's historical exercise of regulatory discretion for these tools.

I also had been researching an article on insulins, inflation, biosimilars and immunogenicity. Will the FDA's pathway switch for insulins and other biosimilars be enough to encourage companies to file applications for insulin biosimilars? What about the relaxation of the requirement for data about immunogenicity, as expressed in the FDA's recent proposed guidance? Will that be enough?

Somewhat related to the insulin question is a topic involving organ transplants. Before the quarantine, the Trump administration recently announced a couple of changes that had the advocates in kidney disease organizations cheering. The first is a change that would allow reimbursement of certain costs experienced by living organ donors, such as foregone wages, and costs for child care and elder care during a period of donor hospitalization. The second rule proposed certain alterations to federally-certified organ procurement organizations. The changes seem intended to encourage more competition by these organizations. I'm not 100% sure that's the right approach; do we really want hospitals to harass patients on their death beds, with the goal of convincing them to give up their kidneys upon death? Another part of the rule seems to encourage organizations to make greater use of organs, even if they aren't in perfect shape. But do we really want to take that decision away from doctors?

Sunday, March 22, 2020

The FTC Issues Warning Letters to Social Media Influencers During Notice-and-Comment Period for Proposed Endorsement Regulation

Regulations compelling speech sometimes give rise to interesting First Amendment issues. 


                On March 6, the Federal Trade Commission (FTC) announced that it had issued warning letter to social media “influencers” for endorsing products from Teami, without adequately disclosing that they enjoyed a material benefit from the company. The company had claimed various health benefits flowed from the tea.

                Although such endorsements constitute private (WC?) speech, the FTC has claimed to regulate the activity since 1980 under “The Guides Concerning the Use of Endorsements and Testimonials in Advertising.” The “Guides” were first “enacted” in 1980, and amended in 2009.

                Regulations compelling speech sometimes give rise to interesting First Amendment issues. Additionally, Supreme Court cases like Expressions Hair Design v Schneiderman and Reed v Town of Gilbert have sometimes been read as suggesting the Supreme Court might start treating all forms of protected speech the same.

                On February 21 of this year, the agency sought comment on yet further proposed changes to “The Guides.” The notice-and-comment period is to end on April 21, 2020. Would you or your group like help in submitting a comment?

Merger of Pennsylvania Inpatient Hospital Services Providers Faces Antitrust Challenge by Government


                The FTC announced late last month that it and the state of Pennsylvania had objected to the merger of Jefferson Health and The Albert Einstein Healthcare Network on the grounds that if consummated, the deal would reduce competition. The agency said that the merger would leave the combined system controlling 60% of the inpatient general acute care hospital services market in and around North Philadelphia, and at least 45% of that market in and around Montgomery County, according to a complaint the agency planned to file in federal court.